Biology 121 section 123

Community Stability and Disturbances

 

Are communities stable?

What does it mean to be stable?

The end of stability

Types of stability

After a disturbance…

Are communities stable?

 

Communities (in the ecological sense of the term) are assemblages of populations of organisms, occupying specific habitat conditions. Sometimes communities persist over long periods without exhibiting any substantial change in their appearance or composition, and when such “periods-without-change” prevail, we often refer to the communities as “stable”. Other communities seem to be more or less constantly in a state of flux, gaining and losing components, and hardly looking the same way twice; such communities may be referred to as “unstable”. We should ask questions about these terms and their application: are they appropriate terms? What assumptions are concealed behind their use? Is there a definite boundary we can draw between “stable” and “unstable”? Are the descriptions consistent with other ecological principles? The present document cannot answer these questions completely, but should help you as you think through the principles of community ecology.

 

 

What does it mean to be stable?

 

Like a lot of terminology in ecology, “stable” has a curious history. It’s a term that we think we understand, but which may not always end up defined the same way by all people. One thing stable cannot mean, of course, is the same thing as “static” – a stable community is not one in which nothing is changing! Organisms are being born, they are maturing, breeding, and dying, and all the while the climatic conditions are varying, small disturbances are occurring, and so forth. There may be a hive of activity, yet over time roughly the same patterns can be observed at the site. Whatever is lost (say, to death) tends to be regained, and most new things (say, chance arrival of immigrant species) fail to become permanent new parts of the system. These facts do not, however, tell us why such a state may be maintained. In a stable population, we know that deaths can be replaced equivalently by births, but how will lost species be “replaced” in communities? The question is subtly but significantly different from the population-level concept of stability.

Theoretically – maybe philosophically would be a better way of saying it – “stable” carries with it a connotation of “appropriate” or even “right”. Whether motivated by the principles of evolution by natural selection, in which we expect the optimum or “best-case” outcome to emerge by differential success of variants, or by the principles of creationism, in which we might expect a “designer” to conjure up a sensible system from scratch, the notion of stable states is intuitively appealing. People studying complex systems want to believe that they are orderly, even if only to have some confidence in the interpretations they make. Unless you start with the expectation that at least some order exists, how can you examine any system rationally? It’s a short step from this position to the position in which one requires order – sometimes, for example in physics and mathematics, students are encouraged to pursue the most elegant solution to a problem, on the grounds that it is more likely to be the correct one, even in the absence of data, though as long as data is eventually acquired this is not a problem. The more complex the system under study, the more necessary it may be to assume rather than demonstrate order, and the harder it is to find solid justifications for the assumptions.

Operationally, that is for practical purposes, we can define community stability in several different ways. Most broadly, we could define it on the community level as “the presence of the same set of species over long periods of time”, for example longer than the lifespan of the longest-lived species present. We could also make narrower, more limited definitions: stability might require not only that the same set of species be present, but also that they continue to interact in the same way with each other over time. More narrowly still, we might add a requirement to the previous definitions: the relative abundances (or biomasses, depending on the type of organism) of all species must also remain the same. The narrower the definition, the more subtle a deviation from it we would call a “loss of stability”.

This leads us to a new kind of problem: if stability (of whatever type!) is “lost”, and the result is a new state, what are we to make of this state? An unstable system won’t be truly chaotic or random – it can’t be. Even if a system is unstable, it will still contain resources, certain atmospheric and substrate conditions, and organisms experiencing those factors and interacting with each other. You can’t call such a system random, even if it does tend to change in unpredictable ways, because it still features the operation of basic ecological principles… just not in such a well-ordered way, or at least not in the way it did before. Now we come to the crux of the whole stability argument: the search for a borderline between stable and unstable states.

 

Back to top

 

The end of stability

 

Is stability, or instability, likely to be the “default” in nature? Evolutionary theory implies the former, but only if the correct assumptions are in place. A stable state is likely to exist in a system if there has been ample time for it to become established, and if there has been not interference imposed from outside the system in the process. An unstable state would then exist where outside forces continually upset a system, especially if the impact these forces have is severe. So where in the biosphere would we expect to see systems which we would be forced to call unstable? Most habitat types, and most sites in those habitat types, experience conditions which are not severe enough to enforce truly unstable states.

All places on the Earth experience disruption (disturbance) from time to time. Disruptions may be severe, but infrequent, or they may be less severe, but more frequent. Some environments feature lots of small disruptions punctuated by the occasional big one, while other environments have the occasional big ones only. There really aren’t any livable environments in which there are severe and frequent disruptions… this would be like the lava-filled crater of an active volcano, or the middle of a permanent hurricane. Thus when we speak of “unstable” states we are really referring to deviations from the stable state typical for that habitat, and indeed in most case the implication is that these unstable states will eventually be replaced by more stable ones (see below).

Now on the other hand, if we see a broad overlap between the set of species that occupies one “community” (e.g. a forest) and the set occupying a neighbouring community (e.g. a grassland), would we be justified in saying that either is a stable state in itself? If we were using the species-composition definition, we would have to say no, but if we were using the set-of-interactions definition we might be able to say yes: the species common to both systems would engage in unique sets of interactions in each community! You can see from these arguments that often there is really no hard and fast line to be drawn.

 

Back to top

 

Types of stability

 

We can define, for convenience, two broad categories of community-stability, based on physiological and ecological principles applying to the organisms the communities contain.

Systems filled mainly with short-lived, fast-reproducing organisms can become established quickly, but such systems are extremely prone to disruption by even mild outside (extrinsic) forces, so they may not ever meet an abstract criterion of stability, but even these systems are stable in a way: they are easily disrupted, but just as easily return to their original state. We call this short-term and changeable kind of stability resilience. It may not seem stable when you first think about it, but consider: as long as you don’t look at the system right at the moment it is being disrupted, it is likely to appear consistent over time. If you know that it is easily disrupted, but also know that it returns to the same consistent state, that is still stable.

Systems filled mainly with long-lived, large-bodied organisms take a long time (usually involving slow growth of well-constructed bodies) to become established, and the process of establishment may be repeatedly set back by inopportune disruptions, but once such systems are fully established, their stability is maintained largely by intrinsic forces like competition. Small extrinsic disruptions are more or less shrugged off by such systems, since the organisms present are physically strong enough to stand up to environmental forces (e.g. trees with very thick bark can “ignore” small to moderate fires). This kind of stability is called resistance (def. 2), and no special pleading is likely necessary to convince you that it’s stable! A disruption occurs, but has little or no effect on community structure, though some individual organisms are bound to be injured or killed.

Of course there are some disruptions so severe that neither type of stability given above will prevail. In the event of an asteroid impact, for instance, nearly every type of organism present before the disturbance will be unavailable to recolonize the area afterward, and contribute to the re-forming of pre-existing communities, no matter how much time might elapse... because they have gone extinct. Such truly global disruptions are like discontinuities in the history of community stability, over which smaller-scale descriptions like resilience or resistance fail to register.

 

Back to top

 

After a disturbance…

 

If a community is disturbed, and it was a “stable” community by one definition or another, it should eventually recover back to that state – but how, exactly? Here we encounter another partly philosophical issue: is there some inherent “driving force” that makes a community return to the stable state? In the early days of community ecology, about 100 years ago, some people seemed to think so. Communities were viewed by Frederic Clements and his followers as integrated units, more or less “superorganisms”, whose constituent populations were analogous to the cells of a body. In the same way that a damaged body might heal itself, so might a community, to return to “health”. Clements viewed the sequence of species-sets involved in the recovery of a system as deterministic, in both their order and their composition. Other researchers, led by Henry Gleason, disagreed, and claimed that communities were not nearly so integrated, and in fact that in some cases it was “every population for itself”, each type of organism simply selecting its preferred conditions, and the resulting coincidental mixtures being misinterpreted as integrated “units”.

Today most post-disturbance ecology – usually called succession theory – leans towards an individualist, Gleasonian world view, one in which each type of organism accepts a slot if it is available and thus finds itself now with one set of neighbours, now with another. Species do well, then fail as they die out through competition or predation or simply the changes in shade or moisture as a system matures. This is not to say that determinism, or integrated species-sets, don’t sometimes exist, just that they cannot stand alone as an explanation. No matter the view you might take of the reason for replacements, each intermediate stage is unstable in the presence of later-stage colonizers, so replacements do occur – whether of one species or of a set of species at a time isn’t too important in the model – until a set establishes which cannot be replaced by another. Thus the process is apparently driven not by a goal but by measurable step-by-step interactions along the way, a much more satisfactory model in science even if it isn’t as elegant as a predetermined endpoint!

At any stage, further disturbances can act to “re-set” the series to an earlier stage, and there is still considerable dispute as to whether an actual endpoint – a so-called climax community – is ever truly reached. In many systems it can be demonstrated that even the “latest” observable stage of a succession is itself unstable, suggesting that if only the environment were unchanging there might be later, still-more-stable stages to enter… but of course this cannot be tested in the real world. A century of theory and experiment has not yet produced a complete understanding of post-disturbance ecology, but it has strengthened the resolve of ecologists to keep testing, since much has already been added to the earlier level of understanding; no doubt more can be discovered.

 

Back to top